“Science may set limits to knowledge,
but should not
set limits to imagination” ~ Bertrand Russell
set limits to imagination” ~ Bertrand Russell
Another important
mathematician, who produced another important and paradoxical result, was the
Austrian Kurt Godel. Where Mandelbrot considered the objective realm, and
applied mathematical models to understanding it, Godel’s focus was on the
subjective – he was a logician, and he was investigating how we form an
understanding of the world rather than what that world might objectively be
like.
We could argue that Godel
and Mandelbrot were considering the same substance from opposite sides – that
Mandelbrot was actually modeling subjective representations and Godel in truth
modeling objective realities; we tend to assume that there is a high degree of
concordance between subjective representations we can all intersubjectively
communicate and objective entities we can all subjectively observe. This is not
necessarily the case, as Descartes found to his dismay, and that is why I draw
the distinction here between the logical models of Godel and the applied
mathematics of Mandelbrot.
When we talk about a logic, we are talking about a framework
in which statements represent either
properties or relations of entities – this is why I say a logician deals with
the subjective realm, because of course the Cartesian theater is constructed
out of these same substrates. A logic consists of axioms, and rules for deriving statements from these axioms, and for assigning these
statements some truth value. The most
commonly understood forms of logic are bivalent,
taking truth values of True or False – and, commonly, what we understand to be true is really just that which we
observe to be agreed upon. This is
not a particularly logical way of considering truth, as it happens, and we’ll
come back to talk some more about the consequences of that later.
For right now, we’re going
to follow Godel in the examination of a particular question about logic: how
far can a logic go? Is it possible for us to conceive of a logic which allows
us to examine every possible statement and assign it a truth value?
Godel was looking at logics
that could describe arithmetical properties and relations; Mandelbrot’s work
indicates that such properties and relations are sufficient to describe very
complex processes in the natural world (indeed, Mandelbrot’s work has
applications in many fields including sociology and econometrics). Accordingly,
his conclusion that in fact no logical system could completely and consistently
describe the natural numbers – and, by extension, the world, although Godel
himself didn’t go that far with it – says something very important about the
limits of human knowledge.
Godel actually devised a whole
new numbering system in pursuing his complex proof of the undecidability of
certain formal mathematical propositions, but we don’t need to in order to
grasp the central idea. We can use a thought experiment to produce the same
result.
Consider the case where we
actually can design a thorough logic for assigning a valid truth value to any
statement – such a logic is programmable into a computer, and allows us then to
build a Universal Truth Machine. Any question we put to the Universal Truth
Machine can be parsed by it, analyzed with its powerful logic, and identified
as True or False.
Suppose now that we test our
Universal Truth Machine, and give it this statement to chew on: “the Universal
Truth Machine will find this statement to be false.” The Universal Truth
Machine can understand this statement, but it can only find it to be false if
the statement is in fact true, and its programming defines True and False as
exclusive opposites. By the same token, the Universal Truth Machine cannot find
the statement true unless it is in fact false. Therefore, our machine cannot give
an answer – cannot prove the statement – and so cannot, in fact, be universal.
Godel’s
genius was in formalizing a statement that can be represented in any
sufficiently developed logic, and that proves for any logic that it somewhere hits this problem. It must,
therefore, be either incomplete –
being unable to prove the Godel statement – or inconsistent – being able to prove that it is simultaneously true
and false without crashing. This fascinating result leads to the peculiar
conclusion that our own brains, which encode sufficiently developed logic to
model the world, are themselves subject to Godel’s Incompleteness Theorem.
That’s a rabbit-hole for another day, however.
No comments:
Post a Comment